Depersonalization. If such is the theme, let us treat it with all due
respect. That is, let us try to uncover its complexities and real or ostensible
contradictions. Likewise let us not overlook matters that may seem purely
technical or, perhaps, speculative, for what speculation aims at is a better
understanding of the changing circumstances of our shared existence, which may
still lack even in descriptive terms.
I would like to begin by indicating what may seem a paradox:
depersonalization is the seamy side of a new collective subjectivity whose
emergence is acknowledged far and wide. There are various names for this
subject: УmultitudeФ and the redefined concept of the УpeopleФ are
perhaps the two most broadly discussed. (With the possible addition of
УfraternityФ with its clearly exclusive overtones, but I will return to this
later.) Without further ado I will now focus on the tension, if not
contradiction, in the idea of multitude as presented by the Italian neo-Marxist
Paolo Virno. Let us linger on the specificity of his approach.
One of VirnoТs takes on the multitude is through forms of subjectivity.
Among other attributes of the multitude he singles out the Уprinciple of
ind
ividuationФ which boils
down to the following: Уmultitude consists of a network of individuals; the many are a singularityФ.
For Virno the multiple singularities are a Уpoint of arrivalФ, the ultimate
result of a Уprocess of
ind
ividuationФ. I will not
pause to comment on the rather problematic link between
ind
ividuation and singularity.
Here I will confine myself to the simple remark that
ind
ividuation and the emergence
of singularities belong to different registers of social being. But for the
moment let us follow VirnoТs argument as closely as possible.
The tension I have just mentioned may be dissipated by the way in which
Virno treats individuation with reference to the French philosopher Gilbert
Simondon. Firstly, let us note that Уpre-individual realityФ is a complex
notion: it includes sense perception which belongs to the whole of the species,
Уhistorical-naturalФ language, whose gradual mastery is individuation par
excellence, and the so-called Уgeneral intellectФ, an English term
borrowed from Marx, which stands for a current image, a kind of snapshot, of the
prevailing relation of production. All of this is
furth
er complicated by
SimondonТs assertion that since
ind
ividuation is never fully
completed, Уthe subject consists of
the permanent interweaving of pre-individual elements and
ind
ividuated characteristicsФ:
the subject is not this УinterweavingФ alone, but indeed a УbattlefieldФ.
In other words, each subject is both УIФ and УoneФ, simultaneously unique and universal. However, the cohabitation of
pre-individual and individuated is laden with psychological crises, and it is
none other than feelings (and passions) that mediate the constant oscillation
between the poles. Now, the collective, according to VirnoТs reading of
Simondon, is that fortunate terrain where the subject acquires a new opportunity
to
ind
ividuate the Уshare of
pre-individual reality which all
ind
ividuals carry within
themselvesФ.
This is where individuation attains, in fact, it highest point.
Such is the tension that characterizes multitude as subject position. It
is then immediately transposed onto and doubled in the treatment of multitude as
collective. For, unlike the УpeopleФ, continues Virno, which displays a
Уgeneral willФ and prefigures the unity of the state, in the case of
multitude nothing is either homogenized in the shared experience itself or У
del
egatedФ to the figure of
the sovereign. The Уcollective of the multitudeФ is seen as Уulterior or
second degree
ind
ividuationФ, and it cannot but establish the Уfeasibility of a non-representational
democracyФ.
(I will only point to the double meaning of Уnon-representationalФ.
Po
litically, it is a challenge
to democracy as we know it Ц both in its theoretical and practical forms.
While philosophically we enter the well-known realm of the end of representation, a theme that may be traced back to the
sublime aesthetics of Kant. And, I hasten to add, that lies at the core of the
contemporary problematic of community.)
I have implied that singularities can hardly be considered as a result of
ind
ividuation. This means that
they cut across existing social definitions and point to other constellations.
Ind
eed, it is a matter of the
other, especially if we choose to understand this other as interpellation or
call. As we know (or suspect), the inanimate may well be singular, in its
broadest scope from the non-living to existing discourses. While the animate may
be split in pieces, virtually shattered by forces of singularity combining these
bits or fragments of a lost totality into previously unknown series. To put it
briefly, individuation works to uphold a set of preexisting norms, it
contributes to a linear image of time, and follows the accepted standards of
differentiation.
Ind
ividuation, to return to the
opposition introduced by Virno himself, would be on the side of the ultimate One
which he identifies with the УpeopleФ. Singularity, on the other hand, would
have much more to do with the fleeting nature of the multitude.
Let me add that I do not think of УmultitudeФ as a chosen concept.
Now that scholars tend to look back in search of alternative political lexicons
and concepts, УmultitudeФ is privileged by right of birth, this birth
coinciding with an almost immediate repression. (Virno suggests that we review
the Spinoza Ц Hobbes controversy.) No doubt, the word seems best suited to
designate a new kind of plurality which does
not stand in opposition to the one. It is precisely this logic that I would
like to underscore and preserve when speaking of a new collective subject. This
is why the exposé on Simondon remains such a promising start.
Ind
ividuation, I will repeat,
can be conceived, in all its
ind
eterminacy, as an open-ended
process: it is an
ind
ividually random trace
(should we still employ the word and its derivatives) sketched against the
background hum of anonymity. (And it is here that I would like to pay tribute to
VirnoТs rehabilitation of two Heidegerrian concepts Ц those of Уidle
talkФ and УcuriosityФ. For him, freed from the negative connotations of
the Уunauthentic lifeФ, both have to do with the mass media and the
УdistractedФ subject which they engender.)
To summarize: depersonalization is not the opposite of an emerging
collective subjectivity, but rather its very condition. Yet, we can distinguish
between Уbackground noiseФ (everything that has been said concerning
Уpre-individualФ givens so far) and the politics of depersonalization. In
the latter case it is the attribution or assignment of names to forces and
places. In fact, it is the political practice of naming
away. (What is the Уthird worldФ, for example? And what are the ways,
after the place has been named, of resisting its disappearance, indeed
obliteration, from the political and even cognitive map? Is the space then void
or doesnТt an invisible УmultitudeФ continue to swarm within it, spilling
over its borders and doing so continually? But this deserves special attention
Ц the politics of name-giving or simply of names.)
Before going any
furth
er I would like to add that
the investigation of a new collective subjectivity is located by and large
within a Marxian framework. Even if УmultitudeФ is defined negatively Ц
either by what it is not or by features such as nihilism Ц it is endowed with
a transformative potential. I will now turn to a somewhat different problematic
in order to examine, at least from one specific angle, what is involved in any
speculation that touches upon the political. And, more specifically, on the
possible nexus between a (political) concept and the reality which seems to put
it to test. Again it will be a reading of a certain thesis, a reading combining
circumspection and a sense of general enthusiasm, and again two voices will be
heard almost at once. I am referring to DerridaТs sympathetic account of the
concept of freedom formulated by Jean-Luc Nancy.
What is called into question (by the one as well as the other) is
precisely the term subjectivity. No
wonder:
Nancy
Тs understanding of freedom is at odds with its presentation as Уthe
autonomy of a subjectivity in charge of itself and of its decisionsФ. Indeed,
freedom cannot be reduced to mastery and/or Уsovereign power over oneselfФ.
It cannot be held accountable to law or to politics, to any one of their past or
present legitimating discourses. Moreover, it defies nothing less than the Уentire political ontology of freedomФ
with its origins in ancient Greek philosophy. And although there may have been
little space for a thinking of freedom Уup until nowФ (such thinking is what
is lacking today Уin the philosophy of democracyФ), it is possible that in
the future Уthe politicalФ, by way of a general displacement, will open up
this space. Which somehow coincides with the УbeginningФ or the
УrecommencementФ of freedom itself.
What is the premise that allows
Nancy
to speak of this
УinitialityФ in terms of Уspecific space-timeФ? Let us note the
following: this same premise will be
the grounds for a deconstructive critique of
Nancy
undertaken by Jacques
Derrida. What Derrida will disclose (and attack) is precisely the remainder of
the discourse of subjectivity (of the autos)
found in
Nancy
Тs writing (and possibly
thought). The premise in question is sharing as spacing. Sharing (partage), a key concept for
Nancy
, is at once, as Derrida
explains, Уpartition and participation, something possible only on the basis
of an irreducible spacingФ.
And now let us listen to the other voice, that of
Nancy
: УFreedom <Е>
throws the subject into the space of the sharing of being. Freedom is the
specific logic of the access to the self outside of itself in a spacing, each
time singular, of beingФ.
Of course, the УsubjectФ here is the УwhoeverФ or the Уno matter
whoФ of singularity.
Ind
eed, as Derrida puts it,
Уit is a question of determining the СwhoТ, that is, the whoever of the
Сwho is freeТ, Сwho exists freeТ, without necessarily Сbeing freeТФ, since freedom essentially has to do with the event
of existence. To the decipherment of the premise I mentioned a moment ago
Derrida adds in parentheses as if it were a refrain: Уthis who would thus no
longer be a subject or a subjectivity in charge of its will and decisionsФ.
I will leave out the subtleties of DerridaТs critique of the Уipseity
of singularityФ, one of the two concepts that
Nancy
redefines and uses in order
to elaborate on his thesis (the other being an extension of HeideggerТs
thinking on time). Here I will emphasize that a future philosophy of freedom
(which is still lacking, as we remember) calls for a radical depersonalization,
if only to open up the space for singularities and not philosophical or
political subjects. For Derrida this will take the form of a seemingly simple
question: Уhow far is democracy to be extendedФ and what may constitute its
Уnon-egologicalФ measure?
Predictably enough freedom would have to encompass the УthingФ Ц anything
and everything in the world that, according to
Nancy
, Уcomes to presenceФ,
whether living or not. As well as the multiple layers of our own УpersonalФ
identity so poorly and provisionally fixed. Viewed in this light,
depersonalization is the equitable, equal fashion in which the incommensurate
Ц freedom Ц is shared.
This brings us to the crux of the matter. Derrida prefers to call it
aporia, the aporia of democracy: what is aporetic is precisely the relation
between equality and freedom. Let me cite a passage which clearly summarizes the
problem: УThe difficulty arises when one must determine politically,
ind
eed democratically (although
one could just as well say here juridically and ethically), the spacing of a
presubjective or precratic freedom, one that is all the more unconditional,
immense, immeasurable [démesurée], incommensurable, incalculable,
unappropriable insofar as it Сcan in no wayТ, as says Nancy, Сtake the
form of a propertyТ (EF, 70) and
actually consists, Nancy repeats, <Е> in exceeding all measure. It is
the incommensurable itself. <Е> The whole difficulty will be located in
the injunction of the sharing, in the injunction to share the incommensurable in
a just, equitable, equal, and measured fashionФ.
The name
Nancy
chooses for this sharing of the incommensurable is, in fact, fraternity.
But this is not the end of the story. It turns out that the equal is not
equal to itself. In
Nancy
this is stated by way of a
parenthesis. He writes: УEquality does not consist in a commensurability of
subjects in relation to some unit of measure. It is the equality of
singularities in the incommensurability of freedom (which does not impede the
necessity of having a technical measure of
equality, and consequently also of justice, which actually makes possible,
under given conditions, access to the incommensurable)Ф (italics added).
Equality, therefore, is not so much a middle term mediating between the
calculable and the incalculable, that is, the world of politics, letТs say,
and the experience of freedom. Rather, it is that which gives/gains access to
the neutrality of singularities whose measure, like that of freedom, is nothing
less than absolute. Such access, though, as Derrida points out, Уremains
itself necessarily undecided between the calculable and the incalculableФ, and
this opposition without opposition is Уthe aporia of the politicalФ.
What consequences does this argument have for our own problematic? Now
that I have sketched out its contours, I will try to highlight and possibly
reinterpret some of the basic points. We do remember that a thinking of freedom
is still missing from the philosophy of democracy up until now. However, isnТt
there something in the world today that equals,
without knowing it, such a regime of thinking? In other words, doesnТt this
thinking open onto a certain reality, unnamed and perhaps unnamable, which is
coming into being Ц into a shared and dislocated presence Ц right before our
eyes?
Ind
eed, it would be difficult to
name it. A neutral zone within the political? If so, then only in the sense that
it is a new alignment or, better still, alliance of singularities, for which not
even the Nancian УfraternityФ (for reasons other than a deconstructive
dismantling) appears as an adequate term. In part this reality has already been
named. I am referring to the УroguesФ (voyous)
in Derrida and Jean Baudrillard,
that is, to the reappropriation of a name produced by the political discourse,
its radical displacement and, if you will, eventual de-naming. Far from being an
act of legitimating an outlaw, it is the calling into question of the law (of
exclusion) itself.
But what is the place for these УoutlawsФ, these УroguesФ?
ArenТt they, moreover, dramatically depersonalized in that none of the
recognizable features may be attributed to them? And how can one possibly treat
them as equals? Their provisional derogatory names are signs of the
УwhoeverФ or the Уno matter whoФ of singularity. They arrive as events
only to upset the balance of the calculable. And as such they are hardly
visible, misplaced. A tip of the scale, a readjustment of the Уtechnical
measureФ of equality and justice Ц all of this is necessary to alert us to
the changing state of things. But there is a kind of solidarity, unlike
fraternity, in this quiet subversion. The anonymous does not cry out for
recognition. Instead, it is that non-mediating mediation, that materialized
schema which links the immeasurable or the incommensurate to measure, the
incalculable to a calculation. Each time a new regulating principle, a new
criterion, a new unit of measure to ensure this access, this moveable link.
The problem, thus, can be stated in various terms: the multiple (plural)
versus the one, the immeasurable versus measure, the depersonalized versus the
personal (individuation). However, it is the status of УversusФ which is no
longer prefigured or given. A collapsing of the opposition? Yes,
ind
eed. Only this collapse does
not simply stand for a liberation or an equalizing of the poles in question.
Rather, it invites us to think through a different logic of pairing and thus of
conceptualizing prompted by experience itself. Our conceptual tools should stand
up to the complexity of the moment. And what we keep exploring, with ever more
fervor perhaps, are forms of collective life that are still in the making.
The sharing of the incommensurate freedom. What this concept implies is a
commonality through what may appear as infinite division or, again, as spacing,
allowing Уeach timeФ and even Уeach oneФ to be other. Singularities
communicate by establishing a relation and yet by remaining divided, that is,
absolute in their very uniqueness. Their solidarity (to pick on the word) is
that of political loners. However, unlike the Уlonely crowdsФ of yesterday,
our time witnesses new assemblages based on a sharing of the commonplace or, to
remember Virno, of УСthe common placesТ of the mindФ, by which he means
a set of cognitive-linguistic faculties determining the human species.
This universality has nothing to do with that of the state. Moreover, it comes
to the fore exactly when the state and statehood are confronted with their
limits. It is both a chance and a threat. Thus, in the absence of a public
sphere the Уgeneral intellectФ, as Virno declares, may lead to proliferating
hierarchies and personal dependence in the sphere of production. But whatever
this state of affairs may become one day, it is already there to
ind
icate a singular and
potentially subversive constellation. Other images and terms may be found for
this changing reality. The point of the matter is an obligation that we seem,
once again, to have in common: to avoid giving names and to learn to recognize
traces of the future in the present.
vin on line . програма для телефона вконтакте
Используются технологии
uCoz